logo.gif (39727 bytes)
 

by Craig Bacheller
Fall 1996

 

But why phenomenology in a class concerning time, and causality? When we speak of time-space constructions, they come to us as culturally sedimented structures, constructs which the architect by nature cannot simply accept as given. "Here I shall argue that at the core of phenomenology, traditionally interpreted, lies hidden a distinctly postmodern form of thought which is simultaneously deconstructive and non-foundationalist, yet retaining the sense of structure and multistability which also makes of it a matter of possible concern for the discipline for architecture (Don Idhe, Pratt Journal Number 2)." Edmund Husserl, founder of classical phenomenology, outlines two distinct paths, one of the "fantasy trajectory" which is composed of the transcendental ego, and the other "material" trajectory as seen in the work of Martin Heidegger and Maurice-Merleau Ponty which is existential and hermeneutic. The critical point is that these trajectories propose the idea of creative variation (theory of imaginative variation) in figure-ground structures that forces the phenomenologist to study the object and its pre-reflexive apprehension in order to get to the "thing itself." What is striking about the phenomenological discourse, is that it forces an (re)examination of experiential phenomena in the world through the experience itself of such phenomena; a critical issue for creators of the built world.

As most architects are well familiar with the Heideggerian treatment of the earth and "place," it seems appropriate to concentrate, for a seminar dealing with spatial-temporal and causal perceptions, upon the work of Merleau-Ponty who deals primarily with bodily perceptions. It is important to remember that Ponty is rejecting the philosophies of both intellectualism (mind-sense construction) and empiricism (body-sense reception) by proposing an inter-subjective, inter-monadal, and inter-sensory perception of the world-body.

 

the I discourse

Maurice Merleau-Ponty and Jean Paul Sartre

Maurice Merleau-Ponty and Jean Paul Sartre were existential phenomenologists who come out or Husserlean and Heideggerian thought which attempts to sever the duality syndrome imposed on Western thinking after Rene Descartes (possibly known even to the ancients as purported by Karl R. Popper in The Self and its Brain, p. 151). I shall utilize the "I discourse" as a means to explicate their dialogue for it points directly to the core of their respective philosophies, and as we shall see, it was their discussions with the "Other" that they were able to develop the "I."

 

Maurice Merleau-Ponty: Relevant Biographical Data

Born in Paris, 1908, he was a key figure in a moment of French thinking incomparably fertile and volatile. He graduated from the Ecole Normale Superieure where he first encountered the man who was to annoy and inspire most of his life, his Other, Jean Paul Sartre. Levi-Strauss, Jean Paul Sartre, Simone di Beauvoir, and Merleau-Ponty were all educated in the academic atmosphere of Paris, described in Levi's words, "on the philosophical level all he had to offer was a mixture of Bergsonianism and Neo-Kantianism. He expounded his dry dogmatic views with great fervor and gesticulated passionately throughout his lessons. I have never known so much naive conviction allied to greater intellectual poverty."

While teaching at various universities in Paris during the 30's, he came in continued contact with Claude Levi-Strauss, Simone do Beauvoir, Raymond Aron, Georges Bataille, Raymond Queneua, Jacques Lacan, Eric Weill, and Andre Breton, and of course, Jean Paul Sartre. These were some of the contemporary thinkers making up the atmosphere of Paris. The career of Ponty consisted in publishing various articles and books with Sartre, in spite of Sartre, and in dedication to Sartre; thus was their relationship as two thinkers deeply interested in the work of Edmund Husserl and Martin Heidegger but in constant conflict and absolute opposites. Reflecting later, Sartre remarked, "Suddenly his tongue loosened. And so did mine. We launched into a long and futile explanation which bounced from one subject to another and from one discussion to another. Is there a spontaneity of the masses? Can groups find their cohesion from within? Ambiguous questions which at times took us back to politics... and at other times to sociology, to existence itself, which means, to philosophy, to our 'style of life', to our 'anchorage' and to ourselves (Ibid., p.204).

"During the fifties, Saussurian linguistics and the structural anthropology of Levi-Strauss were his allies. It is as if these allies in the resistance to Sartrian activism transformed themselves after Merleau-Ponty's death in 1961, into opponents of phenomenology in general, forming heteroclite camp which was christened 'structuralism'."
-Vincent Descombes

Ponty, as primarily Husserlian in his early work, becoming more Heideggerian later, was primarily interested in the return to the 'things themselves', the 'origin of truth', and the world of perception at a time when, "in the 1960's, the most influential thinkers were highly suspicious of the entire vocabulary which spoke of origins, of returns, of truth. Where Merleau-Ponty sought 'foundations' and 'grounds', they found only 'ruptures' and 'displacements.' And thus he came to suffer the cruelest of fates which can befall a French thinker: he became unfashionable (Schmidt, pp.2-5)."

 

The Other is the I Discourse

In Humanism and Terror, Hegel wrote that consciousness is, "essentially a struggle -the struggle of the master and slave, the struggle between classes- and this is a necessity of the human condition; because of the fundamental paradox that man is an indivisible consciousness no one is able to affirm himself except by reducing the other to objects."

The dialogue between these two great figures is one in which both developed a philosophical position in terms of the Other. Thus, each formulated an understanding of "I am" in terms of a dialectically polar position concerning the other. Merleau-Ponty's book, Adventures of the Dialectic, is a sharp criticism of comments made by Sartre concerning the proletariat and communism in The Communists and Peace:

"Each sees the other come to him as anyone at all, that is, as himself. To the extent that massification engenders both isolationism and interchangeability, it gives rise to imitation as a mechanical relationship between molecules; and imitation is neither a tendency nor a psychic characteristic: it is necessary result of certain social situations."

This statement was particularly offensive to Merleau-Ponty and eventually led to break with Sartre. Although on the basis of a political debate, the roots go deep into their respective philosophies as outlined in Phenomenology of Perception (Ponty) and Being and Nothingness (Sartre).

 

Husserlean Other

For Husserl, the world as it is perceived through the consciousness is inter-monadic. The Other makes up a part of its permanent unity and complexity. No matter what I may be thinking (reflecting) upon, a desk, the sun, and so on, the Other is always a layer of the constituted meaning of that object, always a part of that object because it is through the confirmation of the Other that I may establish the object's objectivity. Through the phenomenological reduction, the Other becomes an condition governing the very constitution of the self. My empirical self cannot exist without the existence of the Other, thus, should I doubt the concrete existence of my friend, I must doubt the existence of my self. It is not only through the appearances of others that the existence of the Other is revealed to me, but also on the desk, the tree, and so on, that the Other is revealed.

Yet, since the empirical ego of the Other is just as suspect as our own, it is the transcendental subjects that he strives to make the link between the Other and I. The Other is never the empirical person we perceive but the transcendental subject to which this person refers. Hence, there is a distinction of myself and Other, not through exteriority as supported by realists, but through the fact that each of us exists in inferiority. Consequently, the concrete existence of the other as presented empirically is an absence. The Other is the object of empty intentions (as we cannot know the transcendental subject), the Other on principle refuses himself and flees. The only reality of the Other for me is the intention I direct toward the Other on the basis of the concrete reality presented to me.

 

Sartre’s Other

For Sartre, the other is that person which is not me, therefore having a negating characteristic. He is a person immersed in the being of life. "Similarly, it is thus that I appear to the Other: as a concrete, sensible, immediate existence." This is the manner in which Sartre subverts the traditional fall into solipsism. The Other is not just a part of my world, but is another locus around which the world can be organized. With the entry of another into my perceptual field,

"suddenly an object has appeared which has stolen the world from me. Everything is in place, everything still exists for me; but everything is traversed by an invisible flight and fixed in the direction of a new object (Schmidt, p.71, B&N, p.255)."

The nature of the relationship with the Other is thus dependent on the Hegelian master and slave; the experience of conflict with the Other formulates the ontological structure of our consciousness of others. This is based on the battle of objectifying gazes, in which I objectify the other with my look and reciprocally me with his. "'The best example of the "we" to be furnished us by the spectator at a theatrical performance' who is non-thetically aware of 'being a co-spectator of the spectacle' (Langer, p. 102)." "it is useless for human-reality to seek to get out of this dilemma: one must either transcend the Other or allow oneself to be transcended by him. The essence of the relations between consciousness' is not the Mitsein; it is conflict (B&N, pp.539-59)."

The example of shame in Being and Nothingness clearly describes a pre-reflexive awareness of myself as myself. This phenomena always occurs in the presence of the Other and is a "non-positional consciousness," one in which consciousness is "conscious (of) itself as shame". It is also intentional in the sense that I am always shameful of something "I have just made an awkward or vulgar gesture. This gesture clings to me; I neither judge or blame it. I simply live it. I realize it in the mode for-itself. But now I raise my head. Somebody was there and has seen me. It is certain that my shame is not reflexive, for the presence of another in my consciousness, even as a catalyst, is incompatible with the reflexive attitude; in the field of my reflection I can never meet with anything but the consciousness which is mine. But the Other is the indispensable mediator between myself and me. I am ashamed of myself as I appear to the Other. I am suddenly placed in the position of "passing judgment on myself as an object" because it this is the realization of how the Other perceives me, as an object. "Moreover the very notion of vulgarity implies an inter-monadal relation. Nobody can be vulgar all alone (pp.221-222)!" Thus, I may know myself by way of the Other, and in this case, only by way of the Other.

"The Other, on the contrary, is presented in a certain sense as the radical negation of my experience, since he is the one for whom I am not subject but object. Therefore, as the subject of knowledge I strive to determine as object the subject who denies my character as subject and who himself determines me as object (p.228)." It is through this struggle that I strive to assert my Being over that of the Other. This action would be impossible were the notion of "I am" not already primordially constituted in my consciousness. Through this struggle, I am actively pushing myself upon the world, not closing it up inside my mind. "My body is co-existive with the world, spread across all things, and at the same time it is condensed into this single point which I am without being able to know it. The body is lived and not known (Being and Nothingness, p.420,7). Consciousness is different phenomena than the objects it perceives, even the perception of the body. "I am no more intimately related to it than to other objects I confront.'

Through the struggle, he shows that his consciousness cannot be shut up in its own world but rather "each individual world opens onto, 'a background world that exceeds all its perspectives.' It is a 'partial being', connected to 'the whole of Being' (Schmidt, p.89)." But, ultimately unknown.

 

Merleau-Ponty’s Other

To the contrary, Ponty through his description of the theory of the body as a theory of perception implicitly links the actions of the mind to the body as inter-monadal. That while two separate entities, there is a middle ground, an interactive dialectic that is fundamentally codependent and hence, one may not separate or isolate any one aspect of the person. We perceive the world and experience the world, before any intellectualization, as being in the world. And in this world, we are not a precarious alliance of matter and mind, but rather a third kind of being. Through the complex dialogue of the two, body-mind, me-other, and so on, a third being exists. By extension, there is a primordial flow of existence in which something becomes significant to the extent that it attracts our body in a movement towards it, and our body comes into existence as a body in this very movement, so that the significance of the thing and that of the body come into existence together and imply one another. (Langer, p.50) There can only be objects for us because it is fundamentally impossible to perceive ourselves perceiving; the body cannot be an object for our consciousness (in contrast to Sartre). The body's perspective constitutes our bond with the world, our fixed opening onto it, rather than one among many perspectives seen from some ideal standpoint outside the world. In short, were it not for the permanence and perspectivity of our body, the relative permanence and the perspectivity of objects would be utterly inconceivable (36-7). Thus, I experience myself only to the extent that I experience other things or others. This bodily movement through space then is the very condition for the coming into being (the "I") and the constituting of a meaningful world.

This divergence between the perceived and perceiver, touched and touching, and so on are not in constant opposition and conflict, but rather they show that something other than the body is necessary for a connection to be made, for "there is not identity, nor non-identity, there is inside and outside turning around one another." There is this "slipping in and out" of the two that dialectically create the "I". This "I" is the incarnate subject. Ponty draws greatly upon Paul Valery's statement:

"Once gazes interlock, there are no longer quite two persons and it's hard for either to remain alone. This exchange...effects... a transposition, a metathesis, a chiasm of two 'destinies', two points of view. You take my appearance, my image, and I take yours. You are not I, since you see me and I don't see myself. What is missing for me is this 'I' whom you can see. And what you miss is the 'you' I can see.

Through Ponty's phenomenology, Sartre lacks a third term in which two body-subjects communicate thus hindering him from establishing the bodily intentionality which links my experience dialectically with that of the other body-subject. My placement in the world is not an alienating invasion of the human world, but rather I enjoy an organic relationship with an interacting natural and human world. Since my view of the world is perspectival (I have no ability to see the entirety of the world), there is room for other "incarnate subjectivities" in the world which complement my own. "Their body expresses their intentions and I perceive those intentions with my own; insofar as my body takes up the other's intentions, there is an internal relationship between our bodies Just as in the perception of objects our perspectives 'slip into' each other and are brought together in the thing, so my perspective and that of other people 'slip into' each other and are brought together in a shared social world (Langer, 104-5).

Merleau-Ponty states of Sartre as being "a good Cartesian" who in some places seems to get beyond the dualism, but ultimately does not accept the third term which is so key to understanding the relationship of "I" and of "Other". In writing of Sartre in, Adventures of the Dialectic, "there is a plurality of subjects but no intersubjectivity... the apparent paradox of his work is that he became famous by describing a middle ground between consciousness and things and that nonetheless his thought is in revolt against the middle ground and finds there only an incentive to transcend it" The difference between Sartre and Ponty is best expressed in the significance of the third term which is most clearly manifest in Ponty's discussion of the use of language:

"In the experience of dialogue, there is a constituted between the other and myself a common ground; my thought and his are interwoven into a single fabric...I am not active only when I am speaking; rather, I precede my thought in the listener. I am not passive while I am listening; rather, I speak according to...what the other is saying. Speaking is not just my own initiative, listening is not submitting to the initiative of the other, because as speaking subjects we are continuing, we are resuming a common effort more ancient than we, upon which is saying. Speaking is not just my own initiative, listening is not submitting to the initiative of the other, because as speaking subjects we are continuing, we are resuming a common effort more ancient than we, upon which we are grafted to one another and which is the manifestation, the growth, of truth. Thus the instituted subject exists between others and myself, between me and myself, like a hinge, the consequence and guarantee of our belonging to a common world (CAL,p.354, PP, p.31150, TFL, p.40)."

 

Selected Bibliography

Eccles, John C. and Popper, Karl R. The Self and its Brain. An Argument for Interactionism. Routledge Publishers, London and New York, 1995.

Husserl, Edmund. The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology. Edited by David Carr, Northwestern University Press, Evanston, 1970.

Langer, Monika L. Merleau-Ponty 's Phenomenology of Perception. A Guide and Commentary. The Florida State University Press, Tallahassee, 1989.

Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. Phenomenology of Perception. Translated by Colin Smith, Routledge & Kegan Paul Publishers, New York, 1962.

Natanson, Maurice. Edmund Husserl. Philosopher of Infinite Tasks. Northwestern University Press, 1973.

Sartre, Jean Paul. Being and Nothingness. Translated by Hazel E. Barnes, University of Colorado, Philosophical Library Inc., 1956.

Schmidt, James. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Between Phenomenology and Structuralism. St. Martin's Press, New York, 1985.

 

 

A dialogue between Maurice Merleau-Ponty and Jean Paul Sartre

To be carried out by the seminar Space, Time, Causality and the Architectural Event in which the students will conceptually reenact a debate between Merleau-Ponty and Sartre In order to bring compare and contrast their existential phenomenologies.
Group one is to be Merleau-Ponty and Group Two is to be Sartre
M1, P1 I know myself to exist and be in this room because I instantly perceive this room and my position in it relative to its objects.
S2, P1 Yes, and I know this table, not because I think of this table, but because I instantly recognize it to be a table and can then touch it as it is such for verification.
M1, P2 This is because, from childhood, I have named that object as "table" and in my everyday life, I continue to recognize all variations of "tables" because of the habitual nature of perceiving and naming. This is before I "think" about it.
S2, P2 Thus, it is the intention, the projection of my will or purpose in perception that allows me to recognize objects in my visual field. Therefore, there can be no division of pure consciousness and pure body, they are an integrated unity.
M1, P3 Yes, and this perceptual field you have mentioned, this is the background or "ground" from which a figure is perceived. In this figure-ground, I intend an object by focusing upon that object.
S2, P3 Yes, I see for example the white wall behind you and you because you stand out from the field.
M1, P4 Of course, and it is the letters on your shirt that stand out from your body as a background.
S2, P4 Therefore, you are an object in my field of vision.
M1, P1 Hey, where are you going with that?
S2, P1 Oh, you don't like being objectified by me? You do it every time you go to the bar!
M1, P2 Maybe, but this is because I am drawn to that person. There is a specific quality that is projected to me from that person and likewise a quality in me that draws me to that person.
S2, P2 Nice try, but its more true that we use our body to fascinate the other, only to find out that what we desire eludes us. We have the Hegelian master-slave discussion again whereby I try to make you submit to my will.
S2, P3 Yea, by the very fact that we have a body makes us open to this sort of objectification. But it also gives us the opportunity to break free and submit the other person to a similarly alienating gaze.
M1, P3 But you're missing the point. What about the woman who lost her voice because she was forbidden to see her lover. Or the constant attempts of people to entice and ensnare the other.
S2, P4 Yea, that's my point. We don't want to just possess a body, we want to possess a body animated by a consciousness and in so doing, strip that body of its consciousness and reduce it to a thing.
M1, P4 Jean Paul, you're so dense! Because we are in a constant state of enticing, it points to the fact that the body-subject cannot be completely reduced to an object. The synthesis of the bodily powers is already some sort of transcendence as seen in the woman who lost her voice.
M1, P1 Therefore, you cannot reduce me to an object in your visual field. The entire ritual that people go through in order to "entice and snare" as you put it, is a form of communication in which the two are determining the potential of a third.
S2, P1 I cannot ever know you because there is a-distance from my consciousness to my body. There is then a distance from my body to your body, and then a distance from your body to your mind. I cannot ever perceive of you or my body as anything but object.
S2, P2 Yea, for example, when I am ashamed, I become instantly aware that I, my body, has made some embarrassing noise or gesture. I then see myself as you see me, I become the object of my own self.
M1, P2 That's absolutely ridiculous. The hand touching another hand cannot be both perceiver and perceived. You do not suddenly exist outside of your body to see yourself as I see you. I am not first and foremost the object of an alien gaze.
M1, P3 I have always hated flashbacks in movies for that reason. Its supposed to be exactly what the person remembers, instead we continue to view the scene from the view of the camera only in black and white. I enjoy first an organic relationship to the natural and human world through my pre-reflexive perceptions.
S2, P3 But in watching the movie, we are aware of being a co-spectator of the spectacle. This moment is fleeting and reveals little, but in our conflict over and against the other, we experience ourselves. This is when we know the "I," during conflict.
M1, P4 The dog or cat's gaze does not alienate me while the Other might because the gaze replaces the potential for communication with a repudiation, but it is STILL in itself a form of communication. Thus I become part of the other and the other part of me.
M1, P1 Exactly, the very fact that we have had this discussion goes to prove that we are indeed two distinct but inter-related beings who can know ourselves and each other through the "hinge" which is communication. Hence, there is no dualism, but a dialectic through a middle ground.
G2, P1 No, the very fact that we have argued and have not spoken in four years goes to prove that we are actually two subjects in the continual struggle to objectify and alienate the other. It is only through the struggle to objectify the other that I clearly perceive myself to be.

 

Thus the two must by nature kill the third in order for them to become the third.

 

Conclusion:

The source of the fundamental difference between the position of Sartre and that of Merleau-Ponty, lies in the former's failure to provide any 'third term' between consciousness and being (between 'le scant' or 'pour sol', and 'letre' or 'en-soi'). Sartre entirely misses the phenomenon of incarnate subjectivity- that inherence of consciousness in the body and the world which is the central theme of Merleau-Ponty's entire Phenomenology.

In the absence of such a body-subject, Sartre cannot establish that bodily intentionality which links my experience dialectically with that of another body-subject so that we are able to find the prolongation and fulfillment of our intentions in each other prior to reflection and thereby become mutually enriched. M-P's Phenomenological description of the body and of the perceived world constitutes a refutation ho the kind of view which Sartre presents regarding my perception of the other's body and the nature of our relationship. Sartre must therefore be considered wrong in claiming primary relation is not one between my body and that of the other; that such an inter-corporeal relation would be 'purely external'; that the other's body is merely 'a secondary structure' for me, and 'episode' in my project of 'making an object of the Other'; that 'the Other's body is ...the tool which I am not and which I utilize (or which resists me, which amounts to the same thing). It is presented to me originally with a certain objective coefficient of utility and of adversity. M-P states that like the natural world, the social world is not a 'sum of objects' but a 'permanent field' with which we are in contact by the simple fact of existing, prior to any objectification or judgment about it. He points out that although I can turn away from the social world, I cannot 'cease to be situated relatively to it'. The ambiguity that characterizes the phenomenal body and the social world is the condition of our being human and opens upon us an interworld with unending exploration, unending articulation, and ever fresh discoveries. (Langer 103-4)

 

© 1996 Craig Bacheller

d-Loupe Intergraphics Studios